学微积,讲历史,不做迷路人

学微积,讲历史,不做迷路人

  目前,国内微积分教材,讲微积分发展史,一般讲到牛顿、莱布尼兹为止,其实相差十万八千里,甚胡

是胡说八道。

  请见本文附件。

袁萌  陈启清  12月9日

附件:

Epllogue(无穷小微积分课程的结束语)

  How does the infinitesimal calculus as developed in this book relate to the traditional (or e, 3) calculus? To get the proper perspective we shall sketch the history of the calculus. Many problems involving slopes, areas, and volumes, which we would today call calculus problems, were solved by the ancient Greek mathematicians. The greatest of them was Archimedes (287-212 B.C.). Archimedes anticipated both the infinitesimal and the   (ε,δ)approach to calculus. He sometimes discovered his results by reasoning with infinitesimals, but always published his proofs using the "method of exhaustion," which is similar to the (ε,δ)  approach. Calculus problems became important in the early 1600's with the development of physics and astronomy. The basic rules for differentiation and integration were discovered in that period by informal reasoning with infinitesimals. Kepler, Galileo, Fermat, and Barrow were among the contributors. In the 1660's and 1670's Sir Isaac Newton and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz independently "invented" the calculus. They took the major step of recognizing the importance of a collection of isolated results and organizing them into a whole. Newton, at different times, described the derivative of y (which he called the "fluxion" of y) in three different ways, roughly

(1) The ratio of an infinitesimal change in y to an infinitesimal change in x. (The infinitesimal method.) (2) The limit of the ratio of the change in y to the change in x, l'ly/ l'lx, as l'lx approaches zero. (The limit method.) (3) The velocity of y where x denotes time. (The velocity method.)

In his later writings Newton sought to avoid infinitesimals and emphasized the methods (2) and (3). Leibniz rather consistently favored the infinitesimal method but believed (correctly) that the same results could be obtained using only real numbers. He regarded the infinitesimals as "ideal" numbers like the imaginary numbers. To justify them he proposed his law of continuity: "In any supposed transition, ending in any terminus, it is permissible to institute a general reasoning, in which the terminus may

 

EPILOGUE 903

also be included."1 This "law" is far too imprecise by present standards. But it was a remarkable forerunner of the Transfer Principle on which modern infinitesimal calculus is based. Leibniz was on the right track, but 300 years too soon! The notation developed by Leibniz is still in general use today, even though it was meant to suggest the infinitesimal method: dyjdx for the derivative (to suggest an infinitesimal change in y divided by an infinitesimal change in x), and s~ f(x) dx for the integral (to suggest the sum of infinitely many infinitesimal quantities f(x) dx). All three approaches had serious inconsistencies which were criticized most effectively by Bishop Berkeley in 1734. However, a precise treatment of the calculus was beyond the state of the art at the time, and the three intuitive descriptions (1H3) of the derivative competed with each other for the next two hundred years. Until sometime after 1820, the infinitesimal method (1) of Leibniz was dominant on the European continent, because of its intuitive appeal and the convenience of the Leibniz notation. In England the velocity method (3) predominated; it also has intuitive appeal but cannot be made rigorous. In 1821 A. L. Cauchy published a forerunner of the modern treatment of the calculus based on the limit method (2). He defined the integral as well as the derivative in terms of limits, namely

f

b b f(x) dx = lim If(x) Llx. a Ax-o+ a

He still used infinitesimals, regarding them as variables which approach zero. From that time on, the limit method gradually became the dominant approach to calculus, while infinitesimals and appeals to velocity survived only as a manner of speaking. There were two important points which still had to be cleared up in Cauchy's work, however. First, Cauchy's definition of limit was not sufficiently clear; it still relied on the intuitive use of infinitesimals. Second, a precise definition of the real number system was not yet available. Such a definition required a better understanding of the concepts of set and function which were then evolving. A completely rigorous treatment of the calculus was finally formulated by Karl Weierstrass in the 1870's. He introduced the~>,[) condition as the definition of limit. At about the same time a number of mathematicians, including Weierstrass, succeeded in constructing the real number system from the positive integers. The problem of constructing the real number system also led to development of set theory by Georg Cantor in the 1870's. Weierstrass' approach has become the traditional or "standard" treatment of calculus as it is usually presented today. It begins with the e, (3 condition as the definition of limit and goes on to develop the calculus entirely in terms of the real number system (with no mention of infinitesimals). However, even when calculus is presented in the standard way, it is customary to argue informally in terms of infinitesimals, and to use the Leibniz notation which suggests infinitesimals. From the time of Weierstrass until very recently, it appeared that the limit method (2) had finally won out and the history of elementary calculus was closed. But in 1934, Thoralf Skolem constructed what we here call the hyperintegers and proved that the analogue of the Transfer Principle holds for them. Skolem's construction (now called the ultraproduct construction) was later extended to a wide class of structures, including the construction of the hyperreal numbers from the real numbers.

1 See Kline, p. 385.

904 EPILOGUE

The name "hyperreal" was first used by E. Hewitt in a paper in 1948. The hyperreal numbers were known for over a decade before they were applied to the calculus. Finally in 1961 Abraham Robinson discovered that the hyperreal numbers could be used to give a rigorous treatment of the calculus with infinitesimals. The presentation of the calculus which was given in this book is based on Robinson's treatment (but modified to make it suitable for a first course). Robinson's calculus is in the spirit of Leibniz' old method of infinitesimals. There are major differences in detail. For instance, Leibniz defined the derivative as the ratio fly/ tlX where flx is infinitesimal, while Robinson defines the derivative as the standard part of the ratio flyjflx where flx is infinitesimal. This is how Robinson avoids the inconsistencies in the old infinitesimal approach. Also, Leibniz' vague law of continuity is replaced by the precisely formulated Transfer Principle. The reason Robinson's work was not done sooner is that the Transfer Principle for the hyperreal numbers is a type of axiom that was not familiar in mathematics until recently. It arose in the subject of model theory, which studies the relationship between axioms and mathematical structures. The pioneering developments in model theory were not made until the 1930's, by Godel, Malcev, Skolem, and Tarski; and the subject hardly existed until the 1950's. Looking back we see that the method of infinitesimals was generally preferred over the method of limits for over 150 years after Newton and Leibniz invented the calculus, because infinitesimals have greater intuitive appeal. But the method of limits was finally adopted around 1870 because it was the first mathematically precise treatment of the calculus. Now it is also possible to use infinitesimals in a mathematically precise way. Infinitesimals in Robinson's sense have been applied not only to the calculus but to the much broader subject of analysis. They have led to new results and problems in mathematical research. Since Skolem's infinite hyperintegers are usually called nonstandard integers, Robinson called the new subject "'nonstandard analysis." (He called the real numbers "standard" and the other hyperreal numbers "nonstandard." This is the origin of the name "standard part.") The starting point for this course was a pair of intuitive pictures of the real and hyperreal number systems. These intuitive pictures are really only rough sketches that are not completely trustworthy. In order to be sure that the results are correct, the calculus must be based on mathematically precise descriptions of these number systems, which fill in the gaps in the intuitive pictures. There are two ways to do this. The quickest way is to list the mathematical properties of the real and hyperreal numbers. These properties are to be accepted as basic and are called axioms. The second way of mathematically describing the real and hyperreal numbers is to start with the positive integers and, step by step, construct the integers, the rational numbers, the real numbers, and the hyperreal numbers. This second method is better because it shows that there really is a structure with the desired properties. At the end of this epilogue we shall briefly outline the construction of the real and hyperreal numbers and give some examples of infinitesimals. We now turn to the first way of mathematically describing the real and hyperreal numbers. We shall list two groups of axioms in this epilogue, one for the real numbers and one for the hyperreal numbers. The axioms for the hyperreal numbers will just be more careful statements of the Extension Principle and Transfer Principle of Chapter 1. The axioms for the real numbers come in three sets: the Algebraic Axioms, the Order Axioms, and the Completeness Axiom. All the familiar facts about the real numbers can be proved using only these axioms.

EPILOGUE 905

I. ALGEBRAIC AXIOMS FOR THE REAL NUMBERS

A Closure laws 0 and 1 are real numbers. If a and b are rea/numbers, then so are a + b, ab, and -a. If a is a real number and a # 0, then 1/a is a real number. B Commutative laws a + b = b + a ab = ba. C Associative Jaws a + (b + c) = (a + b) + c a(bc) = (ab)c.

0 Identity Jaws

E Inverse Jaws

F Distributive law

DEFINITION

O+a=a

a+(-a)=O

1·a =a.

If a # 0, a ·- = 1. a a • (b + c) = ab + ac.

The positive integers are the real numbers 1, 2 = 1 + 1, 3 = 1 + 1 + 1, 4 = 1 + 1 + 1 + 1, and so on.

II. ORDER AXIOMS FOR THE REAL NUMBERS

A 0 < 1. B Transitive law If a < b and b < c then a < c. C Trichotomy law Exactly one of the relations a < b, a = b, b < a, holds. 0 Sum law If a < b, then a + c < b + c. E Product law If a < b and 0 < c, then ac < be. F Root axiom For every real number a > 0 and every positive integer n, there is a real number b > 0 such that b" = a.

Ill. COMPLETENESS AXIOM

Let A be a set of real numbers such that whenever x andy are in A, any real number between x andy is in A. Then A is an interval.

THEOREM

An increasing sequence (S11 ) either converges or diverges to cf).

PROOF Let T be the set of all real numbers x such that x ::;: S" for some n. T is obviously nonempty.

Case 1 Tis the whole real line. If His infinite we have x S:: SH for all real numbers x. So SH is positive infinite and (S11 ) diverges to oo.

Case 2 T is not the whole real line. By the Completeness Axiom, T is an interval (-w, b] or (-w, b). For each real x < b, we have

906 EPILOGUE

for some 11. It follows that for infinite H, SH s band SH ~ b. Therefore (S,) converges to b.

We now take up the second group of axioms, which give the properties of the hyperreal numbers. There will be two axioms, called the Extension Axiom and the Transfer Axiom, which correspond to the Extension Principle and Transfer Principle of Section 1.5. We first state the Extension Axiom.

1*. EXTENSION AXIOM

(a) The set R ofrealnumbers is a subset of the set R* ofhyperrea/numbers. (b) There is given a relation < * on R*, such that the order relation < on R is a subset of<*,<* is transitive (a< *band b <* c implies a<* c), and < * satisfies the Trichotomy Law: for all a, b in R *, exactly one of a < * b, a = b, b <*a holds. (c) There is a hype1'1'ea/ number 8 such that 0 < * 8 and 8 < * r for each positive rea/number r.

(d) For each real function f, there is given a hyperreal function f* with the same number of variables, called the natural extension off

Part (c) of the Extension Axiom states that there is at least one positive infinitesimal. Part (d) gives us the natural extension for each real function. The Transfer Axiom will say that this natural extension has the same properties as the original function. Recall that the Transfer Principle of Section 1.5 made use of the intuitive idea of a real statement. Before we can state the Transfer Axiom, we must give an exact mathematical explanation of the notion of a real statement. This will be done in several steps, first introducing the concepts of a real expression and a formula. We begin with the concept of a real expression, or term, built up from variables and real constants using real functions. Real expressions can be built up as follows:

(1) A real constant standing alone is a real expression.

(2) A variable standing alone is a real expression. (3) If e is a real expression, and f is a real function of one variable, then f(e) is a real expression. Similarly, if e1, ... , e" are real expressions, and g is a real function of n variables, then g(e1, •.. , e") is a real expression.

Step (3) can be used repeatedly to build up longer expressions. Here are some examples of real expressions, where x and y are variables:

2, X+ y, lx- 41, g(x,f(O)), 1/0.

By a formula, we mean a statement of one of the following kinds, where d and e are real expressions:

(1) An equation between two real expressions, d = e. (2) An inequality between two real expressions, d < e, d s e, d > e, d :::::: e, or d =!= e.

EPILOGUE 907

(3) A statement of the form "e is defined" or "e is undefined."

Here are some examples of formulas: X+ y = 5, 1 - x2 f(x)=~,

g(x, y) < f(t), f(x, x) is undefined.

If each variable in a formula is replaced by a real number, the formula will be either true or false. Ordinarily, a formula will be true for some values of the variables and false for others. For example, the formula x + y = 5 will be true when (x, y) = (4, 1) and false when (x, y) = (7, - 2).

DEFINITION

A real statement is either a nonempty finite set of formulas T or a combination involving two nonempty finite sets of formulas SandT that states that "whenever every formula inS is true, every formula in Tis true."

We shall give several comments and examples to help make this definition clear. Sometimes, instead of writing "whenever every formula in S is true, every formula in T is true" we use the shorter form "if S then T" for a real statement. Each of the Algebraic Axioms for the Real Numbers is a real statement. The commutative laws, associative laws, identity laws, and distributive laws are real statements. For example, the commutative laws are the pair of formulas a+ b = b +a, ab = ba,

which involve the two variables a and b. The closure laws may be expressed as four real statements: a + b is defined, ab is defined, - a is defined, if a #- 0, then 1/a is defined.

The inverse laws consist of two more real statements. The Trichotomy Law is part of the Extension Axiom, and all of the other Order Axioms for the Real Numbers are real statements. However, the Completeness Axiom is not a real statement, because it is not built up from equations and inequalities between terms. A typical example of a real statement is the inequality for exponents discussed in Section 8.1: if a ;;::: 0, and q ;;::: 1, then (a + 1)q ;;::: aq + 1.

This statement is true for all real numbers a and q. A formula can be given a meaning in the hyperreal number system as well as in the real number system. Consider a formula with the two variables x and y. When x and y are replaced by particular real numbers, the formula will be either true or false in the real number system. To give the formula a meaning in the hyperreal number system, we replace each real function by its natural extension and replace

908 EPILOGUE

the real order relation < by the hyperreal relation < *. When x and y are replaced by hyperreal numbers, each real function f is replaced by its natural extension f*, and the real order relation < is replaced by < *, the formula will be either true or false in the hyperreal number system. For example, the formula x + y = 5 is true in the hyperreal number system when (x, y) = (2 - e, 3 + e), but false when (x, y) = (2 + e, 3 + c:), if c: is nonzero. We are now ready to state the Transfer Axiom.

II*. TRANSFER AXIOM

Every real statement that holds for all real numbers holds for all hyperreal numbers.

It is possible to develop the whole calculus course as presented in this book from these axioms for the real and hyperreal numbers. By the Transfer Axiom, all the Algebraic Axioms for the Real Numbers also hold true for the hyperreal numbers. In other words, we can transfer every Algebraic Axiom for the real numbers to the hyperreal numbers. We can also transfer every Order Axiom for the real numbers to the hyperreal numbers. The Trichotomy Law is part of the Extension Axiom. Each of the other Order Axioms is a real statement and thus carries over to the hyperreal numbers by the Transfer Axiom. Thus we can make computations with the hyperreal numbers in the same way as we do for the real numbers. There is one fact of basic importance that we state now as a theorem.

THEOREM (Standard Part Principle)

For every finite hype1'1'eal number b, there is exactly one real number r that is infinitely close to b.

PROOF We first show that there cannot be more than one real number infinitely close to b. Suppose r and s are real numbers such that r ~ b and s ~ b. Then r ~ s, and since r and s are real, r must be equal to s. Thus there is at most one real number infinitely close to b. We now show that there is a real number infinitely close to b. Let A be the set of all real numbers less than b. Then any real number between two elements of A is an element of A. By the Completeness Axiom for the real numbers, A is an interval. Since the hyperreal number b is finite. A must be an interval of the form (- x, r) or (- x, r] for some real number r. Every real numbers < r belongs to A, so s < b. Also, every real number t > r does not belong to A, sot 2: b. This shows that r is infinitely close to b.

It was pointed out earlier that the Completeness Axiom does not qualify as a real statement. For this reason, the Transfer Principle cannot be used to transfer the Completeness Axiom to the hyperreal numbers. In fact, the Completeness Axiom is not true for the hyperreal numbers. By a closed hypel'l'eal interval, we mean a set of hyperreal numbers of the form [a, b], the set of all hyperreal numbers x for which a s x s b, where a and b are hyperreal constants. Open and half-open hyperreal intervals are defined in a similar way. When we say that the Completeness Axiom is not true for the hyperreal numbers, we mean that there actually are sets A of hyperreal numbers such that:

EPILOGUE 909

(a) Whenever x andy are in A, any hyperreal number between x andy is in A. (b) A is not a hyperreal interval.

Here are two quite familiar examples.

EXAMPLE 1 The set A of all infinitesimals has property (a) above but is not a hyperreal interval. It has property (a) because any hyperreal number that is between two infinitesimals is itself infinitesimal. We show that A is not a hyperreal interval. A cannot be of the form [a, oo) or (a, oo) because every infinitesimal is less than 1. A cannot be of the form [a, b] or (a, b ], because if b is positive infinitesimal, then 2 • b is a larger infinitesimal. A cannot be of the form [a, b) or (a, b), because if b is positive and not infinitesimal, then b/2 is less than b but still positive and not infinitesimal.

The set B of all finite hyperreal numbers is another example of a set that has property (a) above but is not an interval. Here are some examples that may help to illustrate the nature of the hyperreal number system and the use of the Transfer Axiom.

EXAMPLE 2 Letfbe the real function given by the equation f(x) = }1=7.

Its graph is the unit semicircle with center at the origin. The following two real statements hold for all real numbers x:

whenever 1 - x2 ~ 0, whenever 1 - x2 < 0,

f(x)=J1=7; f(x) is undefined.

By the Transfer Axiom, these real statements also hold for all hyperreal numbers x. Therefore the natural extension f* off is given by the same equation f*(x) = }1=7.

The domain off* is the set of all hyperreal numbers between -1 and 1. The hyperreal graph off*, shown in Figure E. I, can be drawn on paper by drawing the real graph ofj(x) and training an infinitesimal microscope on certain key points.

EXAMPLE 3 Let f be the identity function on the real numbers, f(x) = x. By the Transfer Axiom, the equationf(x) =xis true for all hyperreal x. Thus the natural extension f* off is defined, and f*(x) = x for all hyperreal x. Figure E.2 shows the hyperreal graph off*. Under a microscope, it has a 45° slope.

Here is an example of a hyperreal function that is not the natural extension of a real function.

!:llU EPILOGUE

Infinite

Figure E.1

Figure E.2

Finite

Hyperreal graph of f(x) = ~

X

Infinite

Hyperreal graph of y=x

Inllnite

EXAMPLE 4 One hyperreal function, which we have already studied in some detail, is the standard part function st(x). For real numbers the standard part function has the same values as the identity function,

st(x) = x for all real x.

However, the hyperreal graph of st(x), shown in Figure E.3, is very different from the hyperreal graph of the identity function f*. The domain of the standard part function is the set of all finite numbers, while f* has domain R *. Thus for infinite x,.f*(x) = x, but st(x) is undefined. If x is finite but not real, f*(x) = x but st(x) #- x. Under the microscope, an infinitesimal piece of the graph of the standard part function is horizontal, while the identity function has a 45° slope.

The standard part function is not the natural extension of the identity function, and hence is not the natural extension of any real function.

st(x)

Figure E.3

EPILOGUE 911

X

Infinite

Hyperreal graph of y = st(x)

The standard part function is the only hyperreal function used in this course except for natural extensions of real functions. We conclude with a few words about the construction of the real and the hyperreal numbers. Before Weierstrass, the rational numbers were on solid ground but the real numbers were something new. Before one could safely use the axioms for the real numbers, it had to be shown that the axioms did not lead to a contradiction. This was done by starting with the rational numbers and constructing a structure which satisfied all the axioms for the real numbers. Since anything proved from the axioms is true in this structure, the axioms cannot lead to a contradiction. The idea is to construct real numbers out of Cauchy sequences of rational numbers.

DEFINITION

A Cauchy Sequence is a sequence (a1, a2 , •• • ) of numbers such that for every real B > 0 there is an integer n, such that the numbers

are all within B of each other.

Two Cauchy sequences

(a1, az, .. . ),

of rational numbers are called Cauchy equivalent, in symbols (a 1 , a2 , .• . ) = (b 1 , b2 , •.. ), if the difference sequence (a1 - b1 ,a2 - b2 , ... )

converges to zero. (Intuitively this means that the two sequences have the same limit.)

PROPERTIES OF CAUCHY EQUIVALENCE

(1) If(a1 ,a2 , ... ) = (a'1 ,a~, ... )and (b1 ,b2 , •.. ) = (b~,b~, ... ) then the sum sequences are equivalent,

912 EPILOGUE

(a1 + b1 ,a2 + b2 , •.. ) = (a'1 + b'1 ,a~ + b~, ... ).

(2) Under the same hypotheses, the product sequences are equivalent,

(at•b 1 .a2·b2, ... ) = (a'1 ·b'1 ,a~·b~, ... ).

(3) If a .. = b .. for all but finitely many n, then

(a1 ,a2 , ... ) = (b1 ,b2 , ... ).

The set of real numbers is then defined as the set of all equivalence classes of Cauchy sequences of rational numbers. A rational number r corresponds to the equivalence class of the constant sequence (r, r, r, .. . ). The sum of the equivalence class of (a 1 , a2 , •. • ) and the equivalence class of (b1 , b2 , .• • ) is defined as the equivalence class of the sum sequence (a1 + b1 ,a2 + b2 , ..• ).

The product is defined in a similar way. It can be shown that all the axioms for the real numbers hold for this structure. Today the real numbers are on solid ground and the hyperreal numbers are a new idea. Robinson used the ultraproduct construction of Skolem to show that the axioms for the hyperreal numbers (for example, as used in this book) do not lead to a contradiction. The method is much like the construction of the real numbers from the rationals. But this time the real number system is the starting point. We construct hype1-real numbers out of arbitrary (not just Cauchy) sequences of real numbers. By an ultraproduct equivalence we mean an equivalence relation = on the set of all sequences of real numbers which have the properties of Cauchy equivalence (1 }-(3) and also

(4) If each a .. belongs to the set {0, 1} then (a1 ,a2 , ... ) is equivalent to exactly one of the constant sequences (0, 0, 0, ... ) or (1, 1, 1, ... ).

Given an ultraproduct equivalence relation, the set of hyperreal numbers is defined as the set of all equivalence classes of sequences of real numbers. A real number r corresponds to the equivalence class of the constant sequence (r, r, r, .. . ). Sums and products are defined as for Cauchy sequences. The natural extension f* of a real function f(x) is defined so that the image of the equivalence class of (a1 , a2 , .. • ) is the equivalence class of (f(a1),f(a2), .. • ). It can be proved that ultraproduct equivalence relations exist, and that all the axioms for the real and hyperreal numbers hold for the structure defined in this way. When hyperreal numbers are constructed as equivalence classes of sequences of real numbers, we can give specific examples of infinite hyperreal numbers. The equivalence class of

(1, 2, 3, .... 11, ... )

is a positive infinite hyperreal number. The equivalence class of

(1, 4, 9, ... , 172, ... )

is larger, and the equivalence class of

(1,2,4, ... ,2", ... )

is a still larger infinite hyperreal number.

EPILOGUE 913

We can also give examples of nonzero infinitesimals. The equivalence classes

of

(1, 1/2, 1/3, ... , 1/n, .. . ), (1, 1/4, 1/9, ... , n-2, .. . ),

and (1, 1/2, 1/4, ... ,2-", ... )

are progressively smaller positive infinitesimals. The mistake of Leibniz and his contemporaries was to identify all the infinitesimals with zero. This leads to an immediate contradiction because dyjdx becomes 0/0. In the present treatment the equivalence classes of

(1, 1/2, 1/3, ... , 1/n, .. . ) and (0, 0, 0, ... '0, ... )

are different hyperreal numbers. They are not equal but merely have the same standard part, zero. This avoids the contradiction and once again makes infinitesimals a mathematically sound method. For more information about the ideas touched on in this epilogue, see the instructor's supplement, Foundations of Infinitesimal Calculus, which has a self-contained treatment of ultra products and the hyperreal numbers.

FOR FURTHER READING ON THE HISTORY OF THE CALCULUS SEE:

The History of the Calculus and its Conceptual Development; Carl C. Boyer, Dover, New York, 1959. Mathematical Thought fi"om Ancient to Modern Times; Morris Kline, Oxford Univ. Press, New York, 1972. Non-standard Analysis; Abraham Robinson, North-Holland, Amsterdam, London, 1966.

FOR ADVANCED READING ON INFINITESIMAL ANALYSIS SEE NON-STANDARD ANALYSIS BY ABRAHAM ROBINSON AND:

Lectures on Non-standard Analysis; M. Machover and J. Hirschfeld, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, Heidelberg, New York, 1969.

Victoria Symposiwn on Nonstandard Analysis; A. Hurd and P. Loeb, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, Heidelberg, New York, 1973.

Studies in Model Theory; M. Morley, Editor, Mathematical Association of America, Providence, 1973. Applied Nonstandard Analysis: M. Davis, Wiley, New York, 1977.

Introduction to the Theory of Infinitesimals: K. D. Stroyan and W. A. J. Luxemburg, Academic Press, New York and London, 1976. Foundations of Infinitesimal Stochastic Analysis: K. D. Stroyan and J. M. Bayod, North-Holland Pub!. Co., i–

 

评论 1
添加红包

请填写红包祝福语或标题

红包个数最小为10个

红包金额最低5元

当前余额3.43前往充值 >
需支付:10.00
成就一亿技术人!
领取后你会自动成为博主和红包主的粉丝 规则
hope_wisdom
发出的红包
实付
使用余额支付
点击重新获取
扫码支付
钱包余额 0

抵扣说明:

1.余额是钱包充值的虚拟货币,按照1:1的比例进行支付金额的抵扣。
2.余额无法直接购买下载,可以购买VIP、付费专栏及课程。

余额充值